Borel–Kolmogorov paradox

In probability theory, the Borel–Kolmogorov paradox (sometimes known as Borel's paradox) is a paradox relating to conditional probability with respect to an event of probability zero (also known as a null set). It is named after Émile Borel and Andrey Kolmogorov.

The paradox lies in the fact that a conditional distribution with respect to such an event is ambiguous unless it is viewed as an observation from a continuous random variable. Furthermore, it is dependent on how this random variable is defined.

Contents

A great circle puzzle

Suppose that a random variable has a uniform distribution on a sphere. What is its conditional distribution on a great circle? Because of the symmetry of the sphere, one might expect that the distribution is uniform and independent of the choice of coordinates. However, two analyses give contradictory results:

1. If the coordinates are chosen so that the great circle is an equator (latitude θ = 0), the conditional distribution for a longitude Φ defined on the interval (–π,π) is [1]
 p(\phi|\theta=0) = \frac{1}{2\pi}.
2. If the great circle is a line of longitude with Φ = 0, the conditional distribution for θ on the interval (–π/2,π/2) is [1]
p(\theta|\phi=0) =\frac{1}{2} \cos(\theta).

One distribution is uniform, the other is not. Yet both seem to be referring to the same great circle in different coordinate systems.

Many quite futile arguments have raged - between otherwise competent probabilists - over which of these results is 'correct'.

Explanation and implications

In case (1) above, the conditional probability that the longitude Φ lies in a set E given that θ = 0 can be written P(Φ ∈ E | θ = 0). Elementary probability theory suggests this can be computed as P(Φ ∈ E and θ=0)/P(θ=0), but that expression is not well-defined since P(θ=0) = 0. Measure theory provides a way to define a conditional probability, using the family of events Rab = {θ : a < θ < b} which are horizontal rings consisting of all points with latitude between a and b. Rab can be used to construct a function fE(θ) = P(Φ ∈ E|θ=θ), which can then be evaluated at fE(0) to give P(Φ ∈ E|θ=0). See conditional expectation for more information.

The resolution of the paradox is to notice that in case (2), P(θ ∈ F | Φ=0) is defined using the events Lab = {Φ : a < Φ < b}, which are vertical wedges (more precisely lunes), consisting of all points whose longitude varies between a and b. So although P(Φ|θ=0) and P(θ|Φ=0) each provide a probability distribution on a great circle, one of them is defined using rings, and the other using lunes. Thus it is not surprising after all that P(Φ|θ=0) and P(θ|Φ=0) have different distributions.

The concept of a conditional probability with regard to an isolated hypothesis whose probability equals 0 is inadmissible. For we can obtain a probability distribution for [the latitude] on the meridian circle only if we regard this circle as an element of the decomposition of the entire spherical surface onto meridian circles with the given poles

… the term 'great circle' is ambiguous until we specify what limiting operation is to produce it. The intuitive symmetry argument presupposes the equatorial limit; yet one eating slices of an orange might presuppose the other.

Further example

An implication is that conditional density functions are not invariant under coordinate transformation of the conditioning variable.

Consider two continuous random variables (U,V) with joint density pUV. Now, let W = V / g(U) for some positive-valued, continuous function g. By change of variables, the joint density of (U,W) is:

p_{UW}(u,w) = p_{UV} \big(u,w\, g(u)\big) \left|\frac{\partial (u,v)}{\partial (u,w)}\right| = p_{UV} \big(u,w\, g(u)\big) \,g(u)

Note that W = 0 if and only if V = 0, so it would appear that the conditional distribution of U should be the same under each of these events. However:

p_{U|W=0}(u) \propto p_{UV}(u,0) \, g(u)

whereas

 p_{U|V=0}(u) \propto p_{UV}(u,0)

which are not equal unless g is constant.

Notes

  1. ^ a b c d Jaynes 2003, pp. 1514–1517
  2. ^ Originally Kolmogorov (1933), translated in Kolmogorov (1956). Sourced from Pollard (2002)

References and further reading